filosofo del '900
Translated and edited with an introduction by Nino Langiulli, Anchor Books, Doubleday & Co., New York, 1969, pp. LXX-248
1. The Commitment of the Philosopher
Many
times I have asked myself about what the fundamental commitment
of a philosopher consists in; I mean, that commitment that constitutes
his point of honor, his raison d'étre as a philosopher. The
answer may seem facile: the commitment is to "Truth." But aside
from the question of Pilate, which immediately comes to mind, and
without indulging too much in facile skeptical considerations, I
shall say that the notion of truth is too noble, too high and too
distant to be the terminal of a commitment of effective work like
that of the philosophic inquirer whose perspective is limited, as
is the perspective of every other inquirer, by a set of conditions
that act as both stimulants and impediments to his activity. The
philosopher's commitment must find its terminal within this limited
perspective to be effective and persuasive; otherwise by its generic
nature he risks not being committed to anything, since in the name
of Truth, everything can be admitted or permitted. The day-by-day
limited but effective and compelling feature of philosophic commitment
can never be sufficiently insisted upon. Permit me to indicate its
importance with an apologue.
Let us imagine that in a group of people who live by bartering,
there is a man who possesses a great quantity of gold. Let us imagine
that this man preaches to the others that gold is the only wealth
and that he is the only rich, intelligent and wise person and looks
with contempt upon the others who wear themselves out in their wretched
bartering. It is clear that this man will not only be more annoying
than helpful to the others; he will also be destined to die of hunger,
because his gold is incapable of being exchanged for usable goods
or services.
But, let us suppose that instead of preaching that gold is the only
wealth, this man mixes with the others, participates in their work
and their exchanges and shows how the use of gold as money can facilitate
and better the economic relations of his community. In this second
case he will be committed, not to the thing he believed to be and
was for him the truth, but to something more limited yet more effective
- a certain method of exchange - and he will be committed to it
by his daily activity, by joining other men in a common labor. This
is the apologue. Now I do not say that philosophers have often been
comparable to the fictitious personage who preaches the truth that
gold is the only wealth to a community that lives by bartering.
I only say that this has been and is a temptation to the philosopher
- a temptation of the past and of the present which he does better
to avoid, taking instead the more modest but more effective way
of the one who, knowing well that he lives with and among others,
limits himself to proposing a new technique of living, that is,
some new method of thinking, of acting and feeling (however these
words are meant) - not in the absolute sense of new, but
as regards the situation he seeks to correct. Consideration of this
kind convince us that we should focus our attention on the techniques,
that is, upon the methods of inquiry, rather than on the "truth".
A proposal of truth can be taken or left; a method, in order to
be judged, should be actively put to thc test by someone and may
be corrected or improved. It has sometimes happened in the course
of the history of philosophy that a philosopher had to abjure his
"truth" in the name of another "truth." It has also happened that
the philosopher refused and had to pay the consequences. But if
instead of having another "truth" imposed on him, he is shown
that the method be has used does not bring the result that he believes
is truth or that the method itself must, in some way, be rectified,
the philosopher should have no objection, in principle, to abandoning
his "truth". And this is what in reality any philosopher has done,
more or less, in the course of his lifetime, that is, change or
correct his ideas under the influence of self-criticism or the criticism
of others or because of circumstances or facts of any nature whatever.
This observation demonstrates the nature of the philosophic commitment,
and generally of the commitment to any rational inquiry. The tragedy
of Galileo would not have occurred if he could have been convinced,
on the basis of the methods that he held valid for inquiry, that
the Copernican theory was false. The "commitment to truth" is, in
every case, the commitment to a specific method of inquiry.
2. The General Methodological Principle
The
preceding considerations and their conclusion can be expressed in
another way by saying that the proposal of something as "truth"
implies in each case the explicit or implicit proposal of a method
in virtue of which the "truth" proposed can be verified or checked.
I hold that this rule is of the greatest importance for science,
just as it is for philosophy and, in general, for every type, form
or kind of rational inquiry. I do not mean here that there is or
can be a single method for all the sciences and disciplines, nor
do I assume the contrary thesis of tbc irreducible diversity of
the methods. For the moment let us leave this problem in abeyance.
Nor may I stop to argue the proposed rule with regard to science;
this rule, however, can easily be shown, I believe, to have been
enforced, from Galileo to the present, with ever greater rigor.
I simply intend to affirm that if one speaks of "truth" in a sense
different from an imposition of authority or from personal gratuitous
belief, he constantly assumes that there is a method by which anyone
can, in some way or degree, attest or cheek the truth itself. A
method is not necessarily a complex series of operations and calculations
guided by explicit rules. But it always is an operation, even if
very simple or completely entrusted to an organic structure; and
it is a repeatable operation. If I say, for example, "The
lamp is on the table," asserting this statement as a truth, I assume
that whoever is in posssession of normal eyesight can attest to
the proposition in question, and can eventually check it by means
of touch. We may admit, naturally, that there exist "self-evident
truths", that is, truths which are judged such by a glance or that
turn out to be such by the simple arrangement of the words. But
in this case we simply have recourse to a particular method, that
of self-evidence, which, as we know from Descartes on, is certainly
not the easiest to utilize, and entails many logical problems. And
we cannot ignore that many rationalist philosophies, past and present,
employ deduction to confer value on their affirmations; but
deduction is, in each case, a methodic procedure in which the single
propositions acquire the value of truth only in virtue of the order
in which they are derived from one another. Whether the method is
obvious, easy and connected with the dynamism of perception
(though modern psychology demonstrates the structural complexity
of this dynamism), or whether it is difficult to employ and is composed
of operations that can be followed only by those who have special
competence and training, the rule that the assertion of a truth,
in any field and at any level of rational inquiry, implies the use
of an adequate method, that is, of a technique of confirmation and
of testing, remains constant.
The words "technique of confirmation and of testing" need some clarification.
They obviously do not refer to techniques that yield irrefutable
proofs or apodictic demonstrations, although they
include these techniques as limited or privileged cases that can
be found in particular fields of rational inquiry. Nor do they refer
exclusively to empirical verification as it is understood
by the empiricist tradition (whose appeal is to the sense data emerging
from experience) or by science. They must be taken in a more extended
and comprehensive sense so as to include the appeal to every type
or kind of clue, indication, sign, testimony proof, and demonstration
with the sole restriction that this appeal be, in the right circumstances,
re- peatable, that is, testable. The strict and rigorous significance
of the techniques of verification, confirmation and testing which
are found in the sphere of specific disciplincs that have reached
a high degree of scientific maturity, is not excluded from the expression
I have used but obviously includes only tiny zones of the entire
area covered by that expression. The proposed rule is assumed to
be valid by every statement, even the most banal, that claims to
assert any truth. The innumerable statements which make up our ordinary
discourse about situations or matters of any kind, importanti less
important or unimportant, are always supported by the possibility
of recourse to techniques of confirmation, simple or primitive as
they may be but nonetheless fairly adequate.
Such techniques are often simple and primitive only at first glance,
for an accurate analysis may uncover in them a rich complexity of
operations, made quick and easy only by the prevailing biological,
psychological and sociological structures. "Where Peter?" "He's
in the next room. I saw him a moment ago". This means that
anyone could have seen him in the next rooms a moment ago - it is
an appeal to a tecnique of testimony. We all, however, and especially
jurists and historians, know what difficult problems can arise from
the use of this technique. The proposed rule, nevertheless, is of
the greatest generality because is conneeted to any assertion of
which one may humanly wish to give an account. There are assertions,
undoubtedly, of which one cannot and will not humanly give an account;
but these fall outside of the domain of philosophy and rational
inquiry in general. Yet, it is true that when these assertions need
to be justified and defended in some way or their claims or rights
to validity propounded, one merely falls back on the rule expounded
and appeals to one or another of the techniques of confirmation
or testing which the rule generally designates.
3. The Diversity and Connections between the Methods
Because
of its generality the proposed rule can be called a principle, and
if there are no objections I will call it the general methodological
principle. This principle does not permit, at first glance, any
discrimination between philosophie. Given the form in which I have
expressed and illustrated it, it can be shown rather easily that
any philosophy (excluding, however, the extravagant ideas
of the dilettantes) satisfies, in some way and degree, the principle
itself. Undoubtedly, philosophies are often in the most complete
disagreement concerning the methodological technique suitable for
giving philosophic statements their validity. In this, philosophies
differentiate themselves from the scientific disciplines, wherein
the disagreement on this point is reduced to a minimum. But this
disagreement does not exclude the fact that philosophies satisfy
the requirement contained in the methodological principle, each
in its own way.
This principle, therefore, does not permit the negative criticism
of a philosophy by means of a technique of confirmation and testing
which it has not implicity or explicity admitted or has altogether
denied. Hegel cannot be reproved for not basing his assertions on
the technique of confirmation and testing utilized by Locke or vice
versa. This might be done if the unity of philosophic method could
be established once and for all; but it is clear that every attempt
of this kind (the history of philosophy is full of such attempts)
only multiplies the methods themselves. This happens because the
very notion of "unity of mothod" is a philosophy, in fact a metaphysic.
That every assertion, whatever field it belongs to,
must make reference to some suitable method of confirmation
and testing, is a reasonable demand from which no philosophy in
fact escapes. But that all the assertions pertaining to all
possible fields and therefore also to all philosophies can
and should have recourse to a single method, is a completely
different demand which cannot find, in its turn, methodological
justification and can be, therefore, only the postulate of a particular
philosophy. The different logical import of the words that I have
underlined in the two preceding sentences relieves me of any further
illustration of this point.
The rejection of the notion of a "unity of method" in the domain
of philosophy does not imply, however, an automatic recognition
of the plurality, heterogeneity and unrelatability of the methods
utilized and proposed by various philosophies. This thesis, in effect,
being totalitarian like its simmetrical opposite, is regarded, exactly
like the other, as not susceptible of an adequate justification
but only susceptible of being postulated by a particular philosophy.
Fortunately, in similar circumstances, logicians elaborated an extremely
fruitful notion which permits one to prescind completely from the
notions of total unity and radical plurality. The notion is that
of a "family of concepts". The members of a same family are not
stamped with a single, common trait but by many traits or features,
each of which is possessed by only a few members. But the set of
those features constitutes an ensemble of multiple relations that
in some way stamp the family group. Thus, for example, not all will
have the same nose or the same color hair or eyes, the same way
of walking, of carrying themselves, etc., but these and other resemblances
always found in the group will make it easily recognizable as a
family group. The notion is fruitful because even if it were possible
to find among all the members of a family the same sort of resemblance,
the color of the eyes or hair for example, this resemblance alone
should not be hypostatized to define the family group because to
do so would be to exclude other resemblances which should be sought
and brought to light.
Numbers, for example, are considered today as a family of concepts,
and the terms "arithmetic," "geometry," "calculus," etc., can also
be understood as a family of concepts. Analogously, we can also
speak within the field of philosophy and in respect to the problem
which interests us here, of "families of methods" and we can seek,
inside each family, and even between families, various relations
of concordance and discordance, of dependence and rhetorical interdependence,
etc. We should never presume to have exhausted, with the ascertainment
of only one feature, the familial resemblance of the methods under
consideration, but remain always committed to the inquiry of possible
relations in every direction and at every level.
4. The Rectifiability of Methods as a Criterion
We
have said that the general methodological principle does not permit,
at least at first glance, any discrimination among philosophies.
While maintaining the validity of this assertion within the limits
established in the preceding section, we can now reconsider it to
see if that principle contains at least some indication that emphasizes
the importance of some particular methodological technique. It is
clear that, if it were so, this technique would recommend itself
in a special way to our attention and that we would be authorized
to expect less disputable and more objective results from its use.
I believe that some indication of this kind can be obtained from
the principle in question, if we begin with the presumption, strongly
supported by facts, that no method can be called perfect and unmodifiable
(perfect because unmodifiable, or unmodifiable because perfect),
and that one of the results of the use of a method must be that
of making the method itself more supple and, at the same time, more
precise, more expansive in its application and more effective as
an instrument of testing the results which it permits. More generally,
we might say that the commitment to a given method of inquiry is,
also, the commitment to bring to this method the modifications that
its use eventually demands; and these two commitments are, in reality,
a single commitment since the commitment to a method means nothing
but a commitment to its effective use and the effective use
may continually require some change in the method used.
If a method, in the field of inquiries where it is utilized, meets
difficulties due to elements, facts, and conditions arising in this
field, its use cannot be continued and the commitment to utilize
it, therefore, becomes nullified, unless the method itself is suitably
modified in such a way that it can face the difficulties that arise.
It may be that the philosopher or philosophers committed to the
use of this method prefer to ignore the difficulties that it encounters
rather than to suitably modify it and, therefore, to neglect the
elements, facts or conditions that cause the difficulties. This
subterfuge, however, though rather frequent, cannot be considered
as a reasonable alternative and can hardly be proposed as a rule
in the realm of philosophic methodology. All that can be said here
is that there are philosophies which, through the requirements of
their development, in fact achieve the modification of their
method without intending or foreseeing this modification in advance.
And there are other philosophies which admit, in principle, the
modifiability of their methods and include in them, therefore, the
possibility (which they try to guarantee) of their self-correction.
To take a clearly significant example, I would say that Hegel's
Philosophy is of the first type; although Hegel modified his method,
from the Phänomenologie des Geistes to the Encyklopädie,
and in the latter in passing from the first to the last categories
of logic and from the logic to the philosophy of nature and the
philosophy of the spirit, the possibility of correction is not part
of the method itself as Hegel intended and described it. On the
other band, the so-called empiricist philosophies may be characterized
by their attempt to incorporate within their very method the possibility
of self-correction.
The possibility of self-correction defines, moreover, the method
of the scientific disciplines, and this establishes the kinship,
or at least the affinity and the sympathy, between empiricism and
science. The method of experimental observation, for example, which
the natural sciences use, includes an unlimited number of techniques
each of which repeatedly permits the checking and questioning of
its own results. Each of these techniques, in turn, can be rechecked
and questioned so as to try to guarantee, in any direction or on
any level, the possibility of correction. It can be said, then,
that the method of experimental observation guarantees the possibility
of its own self-correction.
We can, at this point, take account of the important difference
that exists between the factual rectification of a method (a fate
which none of the known methods has escaped) and the possibility
of the rectification enforced as the requirement of the method.
The first is the surreptitious modification of the preposed method.
It is made by chance and arbitrarily and always ends, in some measure,
in contradicting the method. The second, instead, not only allows,
but requires the eventual correction of the method and organizes
the method itself for the purpose ot this correction. Only this
second way makes possible an authentic methodological commitment,
that is, a commitment which does not find itself constantly faced
with the alternative either of contradiction or of impotence in
operating in the very field for which it was proposed. We can thus
add something to the general methodological principle by saying
that ít not only commits one to the use of techniques of confirmation
and testing, but requires, as a rule, that these techniques be susceptible
to self-rectification.
5. Methodological Empiricism
I
have just stated the reasons for my sympathy for the empiristic
direction of philosophizing. For the same reasons, empiricism should
not be understood as a theory about the origin of cognition or as
the claim of reducing cognition to sense data or elements, but rather
as a method or, better still, a methodological requirement. The
problem of the origin of cognition may be declared fictitious; the
possibility of reducing cognition itself to sense data or elements
can be rejected as chimerical; nevertheless, the requirement foreseen
by empiricism remains valid. Empiricism can be effectively characterized
only by the explicit recognition (which is repeatedly found in its
historical forms) that every assertion must be supported by a technique
of confirmation and of testing and that this technique must be susceptible
to self-rectification. In other words, what defines the empirical
orientation in philosophy is not a particular philosophic thesis
or a complex or system of specific results, but the explicit
recognition of the general methodological principle and, therefore,
the disposition to utilize, without prejudicing objections, every
technical instrument which satisfies that principle and every result
that can be confirmed or tested by one of these instruments.
Hence derives the attitude that empiricism assumes in its relations
with science, by which I mean not only the natural sciences, but
also the social, philological and historical disciplines insofar
as they have their own techniques of confirmation and testing. The
empirical attitude includes the recognition of the validity of science
and employs its techniques and its results, precisely and only in
the measure in which every science succeeds in effectively organizing
these techniques and thus adequately guaranteeing its results. It
cannot go beyond science in the sense of attributing to scientific
techniques and results a greater value than that which can be acknowledged
to them on the basis of the efficacy of the techniques and, therefore,
to the degree of certainty offered by the results. It can never
become scientism, that is, the exaltation and dogmatization
of science beyond the limits of the validity that its techniques
impose, for it is precisely in the limits and the rectifiability
of these techniques that empiricism is interested. Science cannot
be, for the empirical orientation, a myth to be displayed and exalted.
In science, rather in the various sciences (since a unique and total
science does not exist), empiricism sees only more or less organized
and coherent sets of techniques that are more or less efficacious
for guaranteeing the validity of certain acquisitions and for putting
continually to the test those various acquisitions and the techniques
by which they were procured. It is to this attitude that the operative
sense of the limits of the sciences, the imperfections of
the techniques, and the non-dogmatic character of the results are
connected.
On this last matter w should linger a moment. It is not only empiricism
which utilizes the results of scientific inquiries. Any philosophy,
even the most alien to empiricism (consider Hegel's, for example)
utilizes or tries to include within itself a certain sum of these
results, either by assuming them directly from the sciences of the
time or by receiving them from the philosophical tradition and therefore
accepting them in the form that this tradition has elaborated. This
second case is more frequent than the first and very often takes
the form of the unwitting translation of antiquated scientifle results
into the "absolute truths" of philosophic nature. But it is not
the acceptance of the results of science that is important for correct
philosophizing. What is important rather is the non-dogmatization
of these results -something made possible only by considering those
results in the context in which they were obtained, that is, in
relation to the techniques that have produced them and to the possibilities
of modifying the results themselves. It is not that they are "provisional"
results that necessarily have value only at the moment in which
they were attained. We cannot reject the fact that many or at least
some results of science may be "definitive" in the sense that they
can suecced in victoriously passing the test of techniques that
are in a continuous process of self- rectification. What must be
rejected is the dogmatic stiffening of these results considered
outside of their context, and of the limits of validity permitted
by the testing operations, and their use as pieces of raw material
for constructions of diverse nature to whose solidity they can contribute
nothing.
The campaign carried on against "metaphysics" so frequent in the
empiricist tradition is not only an argument against methods that
refuse to remain open to testing (an argument connected to the very
methodological commitment of empiricism), but is also an argument
against unwitting scientism, which does not ignore science (or at
least science of the past) but arbitrarily uses its results without
taking into account the intrinsic procedures that guarantee them
to some degree.
That philosophy can and should be disposed to utilize the technical
instruments and the results of the sciences is something that implies
neither the passivity of philosophy with respect to science
nor the reduction of the domain of philosophy to the domain
of science. It does not imply passivity because the utilization
of the sciences (within the limits proposed) on the part of philosophy
is not only in the interest of philosophy, but also in the interest
of the sciences. Today with ever greater urgency and frequency the
sciences (especially those more richly developed) need the active
intervention of philosophy not only on methodological questions,
but also on certain levels of their conceptualization and generalization
(as, for example, in the formulation of the "general theories")
and for the demarcation of certain zones in which various disciplines
overlap. Precisely on account of their advanced specialization,
certain disciplines find themselves lacking a common ground to treat
problems that arise in those zones. Philosophy's utilization of
the techniques and results of the sciences does not imply the reduction
of the domain of philosophy to that of science - both for the reason
just stated and because no science nor complex of sciences can furnish
a reasonable motive for this reduction, nor can philosophy ever
practically furnish it. Philosophy cannot set up for itself, a priori,
prohibited zones, except through the recognized impossibility of
penetrating into these zones in the light of the precautions prescribed
by the general methodological principle.
6. Empiricism and the Human World
Now,
this principle has not yet indicated a method but only a family
of methods or, in other words, certain general and formal features
of the methods that can be chosen and employed by an open philosophic
inquiry. Up to this point, therefore, it does not follow that this
principle can be assumed as the foundation of an exclusive
choice, that is, of a choice which assumes a particular technique
of inquiry to the exclusion of all the others. Let it be understood
that I do not hold this situation to be harmful for philosophy;
for if the methodological principle expresses the fundamental commitment
of the philosopher, it would be strange that it commit him to the
artificial impoverishment of the domain of philosophy by forbidding
him, with the prohibition of all methods except one, access to regions
where other methods would be effective; or in other words, that
it commit him to reduce philosophy from the fruitful dialogue that
it has been through centuries to a sorry monologue.
But, if this is true, it is also true, for the same reason, that
every philosopher must in good faith make the choice of the method
that yields him the most fruitful results, and the best choice here
is that of method chosen that does not tend to exclude all others,
but shows itself converging with, or at least compatible with, the
others. Now, this compatibility and convergence can be posed as
a problem and thus directed toward realization only if we succeed
in delineating a common perspective wherein different techniques
can meet and demonstrate their consonance and dissonance as well
as the degree of their respective efficacy. Is it possible that
the methodological principle of which I have spoken gives us some
indication concerning this perspective?
The methodological principle commits me as a philosopher (and also
as a non-philosopher) to give a human account of my assertions,
that is, to give an account to other men (and to myself insofar
as I do not want to make myself the victim of my own errors, illusions,
and fallacies) by means of procedures that others (or I myself if
I want to diminish the above dangers) can understand and employ
with a certain efficacy. It places me, from the very beginning,
within the perspective of intersubjectivity. What it negatively
requires from me as a philosopher is that I renounce the claim of
being the all-seeing eye of the world or the supervisor, would not
have to give anyone an account of the truth that be asserts or discloses.
By committing me to give an account to others, this principle commits
me to consider myself constantly in relation to others, and,
therefore, to consider the disparate, different and conflicting
situations in which I, like any other man, find myself or
can find myself.
At this point we take account of a second characteristic of the
empirical orientation. This orientation which, in its various directions,
employs an entire "family" of methods, not only prescribes the use
of rectifiable instruments of inquiry, but likewise directs the
employment of these instruments in the human world. The two things
are connected and we can express them in a single formula by saying
that empiricism is the attempt to explore, with a human eye,
the human world.
This is why analysis has always been the fundamental methodological
instrument of empiricism, even if it has been understood and practiced
(and continues to be so) in different ways. Precisely on the strength
of its methodological commitment, empiricism paves the way for the
analysis of human situations-not of man in general, in his isolated
and eternal essence, but of man in this or that situation, in the
actual possibilities (which are always limited and not always victorious)
that this or that situation permits him. Empiricism has also insisted
on the limits of man. These limits belong to man from the natural
and historico-social conditions that define his situation in the
world. "Limit" indeed means "conditionality"; and the analysis of
human situations is, in this frame-work, the analysis of the conditions
that delimit - that is, define and at the same time limit - the
effective possibilities available to man in a more or less important
context of testable events.
The expression "human world", wich I have employed to indicate the
proper object of the techniques of investigation that can (in the
meaning described above) be called "empirical", needs some clarification.
In the first place, the word "world" is not taken here as "an absolute
totality" but as simply the more or less indeterminate sphere of
convergence, of encounter or even of the eventual conflict of a
family of techniques of inquiry. A particular technique, if it can
be determined precisely enough, delimits a field of possible
inquiries whose radius is more or less extended according to the
scope of the technique itself (e.g., the field of physics can be
defined in relation to the scope of the two fundamental instruments
of this science: the ruler and the clock). The notion of "world"
in its non dogmatic use (I call "dogmatic" that which has
undergone the criticism of Kant) designates precisely a totality
of fields defined by techniques that are relatively compatible and
in some measure converging. Thus, we can speak of the "natural world"
as the totality of fields covered by the natural sciences to the
degree in which their techniques are relatively compatible and converging,
or of the "historical world" as the totality of fields in which
the techniques of historiographic investigation can be employed,
etc.
The use of the notion of "world" in this restricted and specific
sense implies another important corollary: man as a "subject" that
is, as an initiator of inquiry and forger of its tools, is already,
by this very fact, in the world, inasmuch as his initiative
falls from the beginning under the control of those same conditions
that the inquiry is directed to determining. This is to say, for
example, that the study of physics cannot be carried on by placing
oneself outside of the conditions that limit the use of the instruments
of physics, (Heisenberg's principle of indeterminacy); or that historiography
cannot be done by placing oneself outside of history, that is, outside
of those conditions that the same historiographic inquiry tries
to determine. The adjective "human," which I have employed in the
before-mentioned expression, does not indicate the inclusion nature
of the world in man or the anthropomorphic nature of the world itself,
but just this relationship of reciprocal conditioning between the
instruments and the field of investigation, a relationship through
which the field of investigation shapes itself as a "world" at the
same time that the operations of investigation pursue extended and
perfectable successes.
7. Empiricism in Contemporary Philosophy
We
have said that analysis is the method par excellence of empirically
oriented philosophies but that analysis can assume different shapes
and forms. Because a cataloguing, and an exhaustive critique of
these modes and forms, must, if we wish to remain within the empirical
perspective, be declared chimerical, I shall limit myself to citing
the forms that analysis has assumed in contemporary philosophy.
Herein the reference to a world as a perspective of specific inquiries
assumes three forms: the appeal to experienee; the appeal to ordinary
language; the appeal to existence.
1. The appeal to experienee proper to pragmatism is the appeal to
the use of the experimental method and to the wealth and variety
of human situations which require the continuous extension and rectification
of the method itself. Pragmatism views the experimental method,
above all, as the instrument suited to give coherence, order and
harmony to human situations. It is, therefore, the instrument of
action par excellence inasmuch as it is destined to modify these
situations. The weakness of pragmatism resides in presuming the
unity of method, in assuming the method of some disciplines as the
only one, and in reducing every type or form of human action, therefore,
to the exercise of this method.
2. The appeal to ordinary language, proper to logical empiricism,
is the appeal to the use of the analysis of current language for
the clarification of human situations. The analysis here start from
the structures of a deteterminate language to arrive at the categories,
that is, at the linguistic uses of ordinary language which it is
presumed express ordinary and recurrent situations and are, therefore,
in a position to eliminate confusion and fictitious problems and
to achieve a critical clarification of the situations themselves.
No prejudicial objection can be posed to this type of analysis,
which takes account of the fact that man is, par excellence, a speaking
animal and that all the techniques of confirmation and testing in
his possession are conditioned in general by language and particular
by determinate linguistic usages. It should be observed, however,
that this technique of analysis cannot be taken to be exclusive
of all the others and alone exhaustive of the task of philosophy.
I shall return to this point in a moment.
3.The appeal to existence made by existentialism the appeal to the
analysis of human situations considered as "fundamental" or "essential"
or "decisive" or as "limit-situations"; that is, the more ordinary
and recurrent human situations, which are less prone to be evaded
or forgotten-those, for example, in which man has needs, or in which
he must struggle, or must die, or must live with others. The analysis
of these situations is accomplished by contemporary existentialism,
although in different accents, with the constant appeal to ordinary
and scientific language corrected or complemented with elements
drawn from traditional philosophical language or devised and proposed
ad hoc. Although the appeal to "existence" proceeds analogically
to the appeal to experience, as the memento to test the results
and procedures of existential analysis, this analysis leads, nevertheless,
to the danger of claiming that its results yield the "essential"
and therefore necessary structures of human situations such
that once they are illuminated, it becomes useless to retest them
or to discuss them further. The danger of this type of analysis
is, in other words, metaphysical rigidity, that is, the surreptitious
transformation of analytic acquisitions into the old-hat "eternal
truths".
These three analytic procedures are not necessarily mutually exclusive
and, if we whis to be faithful to the fundamental methodological
commitment, we can and must avoid their every distortion which leads
to such an exclusive rigidity. More precisely, what the methodological
rule requires is that the particular problem that the philosopher
is facing and that he is interested in investigating not be artificially
impoverished and reduced to only one of its aspects, the one that
the preferred analytic technique can deal with. Let us consider,
for example, the case of the problem of morality understood as the
problem of the features and relations of events called "moral" or,
if one prefers, of the function that such events have in man's private
and public life. Understood in this sense that is, within the empirical
perspective, the moral problem obviously cannot be met with a panegyric
on morals and with the claim of establishing hierarchies of "absolute"
values which furnish necessary criteria of evaluation. It will be
a question rather of comprehending the moral events, that
is, of clarifying their significance and perceiving, therefore,
what the function is, in ordinary and recurrent human situations,
of that which is called "moral." From this point of view, the moral
problem will present various aspects. It will be:
(a) The problem of the meanings of the moral expressions in current
language, that is, of the rules of usage of the moral propositions
in this language.
(b) The problem of the logical structure of the propositions called
moral, or, at least, in generali of prescriptive propositions.
(c) The problem of the disparity of moral evaluations and therefore
of the disparity of usage of mora propositions in human groups on
the same level or at different levels of development-a problem to
be considered on the basis sociological observations.
(d) The problems of the relations between morality and professional
techniques, between morality and economics, between morality and
law, between morality and law, between morality and religion, etc.
It is clear that each of these problems or group of problems requires
the operation of special techniques of inquiry and therefore the
collaboration of inquirers of different background. But it is also
clear that none of these problems, taken by itself, is the philosophic
problem of morality, as described above, that is, the problem of
the features and the functions of moral life. This problem is present
in each and every one of the problems enunciated above, but it is
not reducible to any of them. It resides, rather, in the zone of
encounter, and eventually of conflict, between the techniques suited
to face the before-mentioned problems. It is not capable of being
met, in its turn, in its relative entirety, except on the basis
of an ad hoc hypothesis of philosophic nature which the particular
techniques called upon can confirm or deny.
This example, which I have not chosen at random, since I too am
now engaged in such an inquiry, can serve at the same time as an
illustration and as a test of the methodological principle that
I have proposed in this paper.
From: N. Abbagnano, Critical Existentialism, translated and edited with an introduction by Nino Langiulli, Doubleday Anchor Books, Garden City, N.Y., 1969, (selected from: Nicola Abbagnano, Possibilità e libertà, Taylor Editore, Torino, 1956).